THE
24 THOMISTIC THESES
A number of popes and church lawa direct that the
method, doctrines, and principles of St. Thomas Aquinas be taught in schools
and especially in seminaries. After a special statement on this matter by Pope
Pius X (Motu Proprio Doctoris Angelici
June 29, 1914) a number of philosophy professors met, drew up a list of the
principles and major tenets of St.
Thomas, and submitted the list to the Sacred
Congregation of Studies. On July 27, 1914, this Congregation declared that in
their judgment this list contained the principles and major tenets of St. Thomas' philosophy,
especially in metaphysics.
The Congregation itself, in 1916, declared that these were safe, directive
norms. Though the list often does not give the exact wording of St. Thomas, it is sure that the ideas are St. Thomas'. Hence, if St. Thomas is the safe, approved teacher of
philosophy for Catholics, his ideas must be safe and approved norms. A
philosopher who intellectually accepts all of these theses is named a Thomist;
and this meaning of the term Thomist is about the only definite meaning that
can be assigned to it. The theses are given here for convenient reference.
"We admonish professors to
bear well in mind that they cannot set aside St. Thomas, especially in metaphysical
questions, without grave disadvantage". --Pope St. Pius X (1903-1914),
Pascendi Dominici Gregis, September 8, 1907
These 24
propositions are a concise guide of the whole philosophy and can be divided as
follows:
Ontology (Th. 1 – 7) ;
Cosmology (Th. 8 – 12) ; Psychology (Th. 13 – 21) ;
Theodicy (Th. 22 – 24)
ONTOLOGY
1 . Potency and Act divide
being in such a way that whatever is, is either pure act, or of necessity it is
composed of potency and act as primary and intrinsic principles.
2. Since act is perfection, it is not limited except
through a potency which itself is a capacity for perfection. Hence in any order
in which an act is pure act, it will only exist, in that order, as a unique and
unlimited act. But whenever it is finite and manifold, it has entered into a
true composition with potency.
3. Consequently, the one God, unique and simple, alone
subsists in absolute being. All other things that participate in being have a
nature whereby their being is restricted; they are constituted of essence and
being, as really distinct principles.
4. A thing is called a being because of being
("esse"). God and creature are not called beings univocally, nor
wholly equivocally, but analogically, by an analogy both of attribution and of
proportionality.
5. In every creature there is also a real composition of
the subsisting subject and of added secondary forms, i.e. accidental forms.
Such composition cannot be understood unless being is really received in an
essence distinct from it.
6. Besides the absolute accidents there is also the
relative accident, relation. Although by reason of its own character relation
does not signify anything inhering in another, it nevertheless often has a
cause in things, and hence a real entity distinct from the subject.
7. A spiritual creature is wholly simple in its essence.
Yet there is still a twofold composition in the spiritual creature, namely,
that of the essence with being, and that of the substance with accidents.
8. However, the corporeal creature is composed of act
and potency even in its very essence. These act and potency in the order of essence
are designated by the names form and matter respectively.
COSMOLOGY
9. Neither the matter nor the
form have being of themselves, nor are they produced or corrupted of
themselves, nor are they included in any category otherwise than reductively, as
substantial principles.
10. Although extension in quantitative parts follows
upon a corporeal nature, nevertheless it is not the same for a body to be a
substance and for it to be quantified. For of itself substance is indivisible,
not indeed as a point is indivisible, but as that which falls outside the order
of dimensions is indivisible. But quantity, which gives the substance
extension, really differs from the substance and is truly an accident.
11. The principle of individuation, i.e., of numerical
distinction of one individual from another with the same specific nature, is
matter designated by quantity. Thus in pure spirits there cannot be more than
individual in the same specific nature.
12. By virtue of a body's quantity itself, the body is
circumscriptively in a place, and in one place alone circumscriptively, no
matter what power might be brought to bear.
13. Bodies are
divided into two groups; for some are living and others are devoid of life. In
the case of the living things, in order that there be in the same subject an
essentially moving part and an essentially moved part, the substantial form,
which is designated by the name soul, requires an organic disposition, i.e.
heterogeneous parts.
PSYCHOLOGY
14. Souls in the vegetative and sensitive orders cannot subsist of
themselves, nor are they produced of themselves. Rather, they are no more than
principles whereby the living thing exists and lives; and since they are wholly
dependent upon matter, they are incidentally corrupted through the corruption
of the composite.
15. On the other hand, the human soul subsists of
itself. When it can be infused into a sufficiently disposed subject, it is
created by God. By its very nature, it is incorruptible and immortal.
16. This rational soul is united to the body in such a
manner that it is the only substantial form of the body. By virtue of his soul a man is a man, an
animal, a living thing, a body, a substance and a being. Therefore the soul gives
man every essential degree of perfection; moreover, it gives the body a share
in the act of being whereby it itself exists.
17. From the human soul there naturally issue forth
powers pertaining to two orders, the organic and the non-organic. The organic
powers, among which are the senses, have the composite as their subject. The
non-organic powers have the soul alone as their subject. Hence, the intellect
is a power intrinsically independent of any bodily organ.
18. Intellectuality necessarily follows upon
immateriality, and furthermore, in such manner that the father the distance
from matter, the higher the degree of intellectuality. Any being is the
adequate object of understanding in general. But in the present state of union
of soul and body, quiddities abstracted from the material conditions of
individuality are the proper object of the human intellect.
19. Therefore, we receive knowledge from sensible
things. But since sensible things are not actually intelligible, in addition to
the intellect, which formally understands, an active power must be acknowledged
in the soul, which power abstracts intelligible likeness or species from sense
images in the imagination.
20. Through these intelligible likenesses or species we
directly know universals, i.e. the natures of things. We attain to singulars by
our senses, and also by our intellect, when it beholds the sense images. But we
ascend to knowledge of spiritual things by analogy.
21. The will does not precede the intellect but follows
upon it. The will necessarily desires that which is presented to it as a good
in every respect satisfying the appetite. But it freely chooses among the many
goods that are presented to it as desirable according to a changeable judgment
or evaluation. Consequently, the choice follows the final practical judgment.
But the will is the cause of it being the final one.
THEODICY
22. We do not perceive by an immediate intuition that God exists, nor
do we prove it a priori. But we do prove it a posteriori, i.e., from the things
that have been created, following an argument from the effects to the cause:
namely, from things which are moved and cannot be the adequate source of their
motion, to a first unmoved mover; from the production of the things in this
world by causes subordinated to one another, to a first uncaused cause; from
corruptible things which equally might be or not be, to an absolutely necessary
being; from things which more or less are, live, and understand, according to
degrees of being, living and understanding, to that which is maximally
understanding, maximally living and maximally a being; finally, from the order
of all things, to a separated intellect which has ordered and organized things,
and directs them to their end.
23. The metaphysical motion of the Divine Essence is
correctly expressed by saying that it is identified with the exercised
actuality of its won being, or that it is subsistent being itself. And this is
the reason for its infinite and unlimited perfection.
24. By reason of the very purity of His being, God is
distinguished from all finite beings. Hence it follows, in the first place,
that the world could only have come from God by creation; secondly, that not
even by way of a miracle can any finite nature be given creative power, which of
itself directly attains the very being of any being; and finally, that no
created agent can in any way influence the being of any effect unless it has
itself been moved by the first Cause.
In 1917,
publishing the Canon Law, Pope Benedict XV ordered the method, doctrines and
principles of St Thomas to be followed (Code, can. 1366, § 2) and gave as
reference the decree of the Sacred Congregation approving the 24 Thesis.
Acta Apostolicae Sedis, Vl (1914), 38386, is the source of the list of theses.
It evaluates them as a good statement of the principles and major views of St. Thomas' philosophy.
The same Acta, VII (1916), 15758, refers to them as safe, directive
norms.
CATHOLIC APOLOGETICS INFORMATION